Doi: https://doi.org/10.17398/2340-4256.15.763
DO WE NEED A THEOLOGY OF
SCIENCE?
¿Necesitamos una teología de la ciencia?
Michał Oleksowicz
Nicolaus
Copernicus University
Recibido:
08/10/2019 Aceptado: 22/12/2019
Abstract
In
this article we discuss the specificity and importance of the idea of theology
of science proposed by the philosopher and theologian Michał Heller. The
salient features of the definition of this discipline are summarily
reconstructed, explaining the main themes that the theology of science would
deal with and presenting some objections to this definition. It is emphasized
that the theology of science, especially in the case of the contingency of the
world and of its intelligibility, can consider the limits of the empirical
method. Moreover, methodological aspects of the discipline are discussed in the
context of different representations of the science-theology relationship,
highlighting the scope and the limits of the theology of science. Above two
approaches are analysed: the methodological model of separation (isolationism),
and the anti-separationist model (interactionism). It is noted that the
theology of science could be a particular type of inductive metaphysics, which
works on scientific and theological extrapolations. Therefore, in the theology
of science, the special task for philosophy would be making more clear the
speculative space within which to carry out the mediation between science and
theology. At the end some epistemological observations and proposals are made
for the further development of the discipline. All this would imply the need
for the elaboration of hypothetical theology that would help in the study of
the new theological problems.
Keywords: Theology of science, isolationism, interactionism, science-theology
relationship.
Resumen
En
este artículo discutimos la especificidad e importancia de la idea de la
teología de la ciencia propuesta por el filósofo y teólogo Michał Heller. Se
reconstruyen sumariamente los rasgos más destacados de la definición de esta
disciplina, explicando los principales temas que trataría la teología de la
ciencia y presentando algunas objeciones a esta definición. Se hace hincapié en
que la teología de la ciencia, especialmente en el caso de la contingencia del
mundo y de su inteligibilidad, puede considerar los límites del método
empírico. Además, los aspectos metodológicos de la disciplina se examinan en el
contexto de diferentes representaciones de la relación entre ciencia y
tecnología, poniendo de relieve el alcance y los límites de la teología de la ciencia.
Se analizan dos enfoques: el modelo metodológico de separación (aislacionismo)
y el modelo antiseparacionista (interaccionismo). Se señala que la teología de
la ciencia podría ser un tipo particular de metafísica inductiva, que trabaja
sobre extrapolaciones científicas y teológicas. Por lo tanto, en la teología de
la ciencia, la tarea especial de la filosofía sería hacer más claro el espacio
especulativo en el que llevar a cabo la mediación entre la ciencia y la
teología. Al final se hacen algunas observaciones y propuestas epistemológicas
para el desarrollo ulterior de la disciplina. Todo ello implicaría la necesidad
de la elaboración de una hipotética teología que ayudaría al estudio de los
nuevos problemas teológicos.
Palabras clave: Teología de la ciencia, aislacionismo, interaccionismo, relación
ciencia-teología.
I. Introduction
Some authors pay
attention to the fact that modern theology follows the growing specialization
of the various disciplines (e.g. theology of liberation, of ecology, etc.),
which could lead to the risk of depriving theological reflection its proper
content (Roszak 2014; Woźniak 2007). In this context, we will consider the
value and necessity of the idea of theology of science proposed by Michał
Heller (Tarnów, 1936-), a polish philosopher, who is known as a physicist and
cosmologist, but also as a philosopher of nature, physics and as well an expert
in the field of Science and Religion. He received the Templeton Prize in
2008 (Heller 2008a).
The problem of establishing
what type of relations exist between theology and science is a very serious one
which has been present in European thought for many centuries. Considering the
high degree of interest in the empirical-mathematical and technological
sciences in Western culture, it can also be defined as existential, because of
splitting the intellectual life into two polar groups: humanistic and
scientific. In fact it seems that we are now far from those epochs in which
theology dominated (guided) other disciplines. Today it seems that theology and
science often demarcate their areas of research by professing “a pact of
non-intervention”. This situation probably arose due to the strong criticism
(starting from modern times) of that intermediary between science and theology
which had before been represented by metaphysics (Koyré 2018). Consequently, if
theology and science remain separated, this discord requires a type of
reflection especially from philosophy and science-engaged theology. As
emphasized by Lambert, philosophy can and should play the role of the
hermeneutics of scientific results that traces the common ground between
science and theology, exploring the boundaries of concepts and making them
usable within theology (Lambert 1999, 126-130; Lambert 2002, 13-15).
This paper contends
that the analysis of scientific realism can uncover implications for the
theology of science program as proposed by Michał Heller. The starting point is
the ongoing lively debate between realism and antirealism amid the philosophy of
science. It is beyond the scope of this paper to discuss in detail the various
problems linked to this debate, but it is sufficient to note that, according to
the core idea of many philosophers of science, continuous development of
science would speak towards a realistic interpretation of scientific theories.
It is commonly thought that the most powerful argument towards scientific
realism is the no miracles argument, “according to which the success of science would be miraculous if
scientific theories were not at least approximately true descriptions of the
world” (Ladyman 2014). Despite the underdetermination argument,
frequently quoted as providing a basis for scepticism towards the unobservable
entities theory, probably the strongest arguments against scientific realism
are so called historical objections, of which the most widely known is the
pessimistic meta-induction (Pietsch 2011). Ontological discontinuity, seen in
consequent scientific theories, seems to give the foundation not only for mere
agnosticism but for a positive belief, i.e. that many of the core theoretical
terms of today’s scientific theories will be considered obsolete in the future.
This is an induction-based reasoning that our current best theories will be
substituted by new theories and consequently, some of the core theoretical
terms of today’s best theories will be substituted by others. That is why the
question of approximate truth discovery and an ontological reference of
theoretical terms from our best current theories would be subjected to doubt (Alai
2017).
Even if there is no
unanimous agreement on the “form” of realism among those who defend standard
realism in the face of historical objections, some form of philosophical (or
theological) realism could remain undisputed by the theory of discontinuity. On
the other hand, science-engaged theology is interested in the issue of realism,
because in the theological perspective, the world is God’s work and in some way
it reflects God’s goodness and wisdom (Strumiłowski 2019). It seems that
because in the context of contemporary philosophy of science, the problem of
ontological discontinuity of scientific theories is widely discussed, one would
need a possible heuristic role for the theology of science in this debate. In
other words, the theological attempt to complete a philosophical discussion
around the problem of temporality of science, would be based on some
theological assumptions deriving from the understanding the world as the Work
of God and on the analysis of the ontological image of the world present in the
philosophical and theological thought. Thus in this context arises a question
about the principal theological/philosophical assumption of rationality of
science and the world (Heller 2006).
II. The theology of science
1. Foundation of Dialogue
In the light of the
above mentioned “pact of non-intervention” and opportunities that are arising
from an ongoing lively debate between realism and antirealism amid the
philosophy of science, it should be noted that, according to Heller’s
philosophy, theology and science have always been intertwined and the strong
demarcation between them had, as history shows, a negative effect on both (Heller
1987a; Heller 2008b, 21-23, 49-53; Heller 2014, 41-120; Pedersen 1990, 139-160;
Pedersen 1997). As a common denominator for the possibility of dialogue between
the disciplines, Heller considers the question of rationality, or the mystery
of the intelligibility (comprehensibility) of the world (Heller 2015a).
It can be noted
that from the theological point of view, the created world is impregnated with
a sense (meaning) and values. To avoid confusion, Heller proposes that we use
the term “meaning” in reference to linguistic expressions, and the term “sense”
referring to extralinguistic objects. He explains that we ascribe sense to
objects (“sense for someone”), where sense becomes a type of value (with
certain epistemic aspect). Heller points out that mathematical structures have
a syntactic meaning, but when they are used for modelling the world they also
evoke a semantic sense. We can therefore speak not only of the sense of certain
models, but also of the sense of whole theories. In this way, scientists can
speak of the harmony or beauty of mathematical structures, or indeed, of all science.
Because theories address some aspects of the world, one may also speak of the
sense of the Universe. This sense would consist in the harmony of the world and
in the fact that the world can be studied by the mathematical method. Heller
points out that his reasoning is two-fold: 1) we attribute to the world sense
on the basis of the empirical method; 2) the universe looks like a harmonious
Totality, which is knowable. Moreover, Heller shows that in our days there is a
widespread debate on epistemic values in science (e.g. consistency,
concordance with empirical data, simplicity, mathematical elegance). However,
in the theological perspective, this sense and these values would find their
foundation in the divine Logos
(Sense) (Heller 1997; Heller 2007; Heller 2008b, 168-208). We note that all
science is based on the idea of some kind of rationality and stability of
nature. Thus it seems that the theme of Logos
and rationality can create bridges between the sciences and theology/ philosophy.
Even if Heller does
not address in any deep way the philosophical problematic of sense and values,
it seems that the proposal of Lambert, with his idea of the articulation of
theology and science on the ontological (where the key concept would be the
final cause and the problem of being), epistemological (with the central
question of metaphysical presuppositions of science and the search for unity
and the sense of nature) and ethical level (the critical reflection on the
ethical implications of scientific activity) (Lambert 1999, 106-125), could be
seen as the right direction to continue what Heller first outlined. In this way
theology could “help to interpret the intelligibility of nature as a sign of a
gift received, a manifestation of its very purpose: to understand that unique
is the Foundation of what is visible and invisible, that unique is the
reference to a Subject in relation with the Cosmos” (Marcacci 2018a, 163).
2. The core idea of the
theology of science
Michał Heller
presented the foundations of the theology of science project in his book Nowa fizyka i nowa teologia (Heller 2014, 150-154), based on
ideas which he formulated in the 1980s. In fact, the first publication that
explained this concept was the post-congress text of his friend and
collaborator Josef Życiński, after the Second Interdisciplinary Seminary at
Castel Gandolfo in 1982 (Życiński 1984, 85). Basically, Heller describes
theology of science as a theological afterthought on sciences, which would
examine consequences of the fact that empirical sciences research the world
created by God.
In the starting
point of his thought, this polish cosmologist emphasized that the universe of
science is merely a part of the universe of theology, which means that the
material world, from a theological perspective, is richer than the same world
as seen from the perspective of empirical sciences, because theology can make
statements on the “material world” which do not fit within the limits of
empirical method. This means that the theology of science should look at
science through the eyes of a well-informed theologian. Theology of science
should be a part of the theology of values (sense), and use results from the
philosophy of science. It would not have a directly apologetic character, but
would rather aim at the enrichment of the perception of science, taking into
consideration those aspects that are only visible using the theological method (Heller
2015b, 13-18; Heller 2016, 311-312).
Therefore, as
suggested by Szczurek, one can describe the theology of science as a
theological discipline which interprets scientific research results, as
developed by philosophy of science, in the light of details of Revelation and
the final objective of man (Szczurek 2015, 133-134). As a consequence, the
material matter of theology of science would be the existence of sciences,
their basic tenants, methods and results; its formal matter – relation of such
defined object with transcendence, the meaning that results from it concerning
God and man. Bugajak clarifies that the project of the theology of science
would be an attempt to refine and deepen a discourse present in a field called Science
and Religion (Bugajak 2015, 145-146). This deals with pointing out
implications that the content of scientific theories can bring towards theology
and religion. Meanwhile, a theology of science would be a theological reflexion
on meta-objective aspects of science among which one can be described as
methodological (way of practising science) and the other one as “existential”
(the fact of existence of science as a way of gaining knowledge).
On the way towards
the implementation of this discipline, remarks from Dadaczyński are
particularly helpful (Dadaczyński 2015, 76-79). He lists some elements
characteristic for the theology of science. Firstly, the theology of science
embraces the assumptions of theology (i.e. it refers to theological sources
pointed out by Melchior Cano) and if it is articulated in a catholic environment,
it is to be supervised by the Magisterium of Church. Secondly, it is a
reflection performed at a meta-level. The need to perform a theology of science
on meta-scientific level results from the fact that on such level one can
reflect on some of the aspects of scientific cognition. This level can be
conceived of as supplementary to philosophy of science in its ontological
layer. In fact, since science uses mathematical and empirical methods and
theology uses natural language, this means that statements from science are not
directly transferred onto a level of theology of science but can be subject to
philosophical analysis from within a theology of science. Thirdly, it is
advisable to assume that a theology of science will provide a fresh view on
certain problems, rather than attempting to build a new theological system. It
may be necessary, in analyses of theology of science, to call upon theological
hypotheses.
3. The fundamental issues of
the theology of science
As highlighted by
Heller, the philosophy of science analyses the limits of possibilities for
empirical inquiry, but due to its nature, it cannot transcend these limits.
Meanwhile theology of science, especially in the context of the two features of
the world, would be able to look at the empirical limits from the other side so
to speak, the side not accessible by sciences. The first of these features is
the contingency of the world, that is, its existence as being dependent upon
the Creator. The other one is the fact that world is full of values in regard
to which empirical method is generally insensitive.
As pointed out by
Heller, if the key issues investigated by theology of science should be the
issue of theological concept of the creation of the world (Heller 1987b; Heller
2014, 157-161), a question then arises on how the theology of creation, which
undoubtedly uses metaphysical models for expressing content of the Revelation,
could be enhanced by calling upon the scientific data? Although theology is a
reflexion on the content of the Revelation and not on science, such reflexion
has to be performed in the context of understanding created by science.
Moreover, if theology is supposed to have an anthropological value, it cannot
resign from dialogue with science, which is one of the necessary conditions for
understanding man. Since previous metaphysical enquiries were based mainly on
common experience, it seems that in the context of the development of science
which touches subjects like the ontology of quantum and sub-quantum areas,
there is a need for new reflections regarding current metaphysical views.
Moreover, the
problem of the rationality of the world, which is the feature that enables
rational research, is strictly connected to the theology of creation.
Theological reflection can investigate this question on its own, although a
theology of science can be introduced in order to undertake the subject of
“God’s plan” in the creation, which is fundamental for theology of creation.
The problem of the
rationality of science is closely linked to the previous issue of the
rationality of the world. In other words, it seems appropriate that the
theology of science tries to answer more explicitly the question “why should we
do science?”. From the theological point of view, man is a mortal being, but called
to eternity, so theology assigns to man a certain teleology of existence
(salvation). This is why theology can formulate certain teleological judgments
on science. Science plays an auxiliary role for man, that he may dominate the
earth (Genesis 1,28). It seems, therefore, that the main objective of science
is not only to know the truth as such, but also to rule the world (pragmatic
aspect) (Olszewski 2015, 98-99).
III. Discussion
1. Methodological comments
In this section
various representations of the science-theology relationship will be reviewed
by highlighting the scope and limits of the theology of science (Russell 2002).
Polak, in his discussion of the method of theology of science, in reference to
Barbour’s classic systematization, suggested that in case of theology of
science, it is relevant to analyse two approaches: methodological separation
model (isolationism) which assumes a methodological difference between theology
and nature sciences which results in the independence of both sciences; and
anti-separationistic model (interactionism) which hopes to create a theological
method which would accept some of the elements of nature sciences method (Barbour
1997, 77-136; Polak 2015, 25-29). In case of the program of theology of
science, two essential questions arise: how is it possible to break barriers
between the disciplines (discordism) and how is it possible to avoid extreme
integrationism (concordism)?
From an interaction
point of view, Heller and Życiński maintain the existence of a common ground
between theology and nature sciences. According to Heller, theology and science
have the same area of interest, the Universe, however they see it in a
different way. As such, science would act as locus theologicus, pointing to interconnection between theology of
science and science. Moreover, theology of science would show the world as
existing through dependence upon the Creator and allow for approaching its
axiological dimension. According to Polak, Heller did not clarify why the
reflexion upon values should be done by theology and not by philosophy. In
other words, is it, according to Heller, only theology that can deliver
substantiation of axiology of nature? (Polak 2015, 29-35).
Macek proposed an
interpretation of the program of theology of science in an interdisciplinary
spirit (Macek 2010; Macek 2011). For Życiński, who assumes an
anti-separationistic view, the area of integration should be philosophical
reflection, which points to transdisciplinary activity. It is hard to ascertain
whether Heller’s view of theology of science is more similar to
multidisciplinary or interdisciplinary action (Polak 2015, 35-40).
Turek, on the other
hand, describes Heller’s views as efforts towards assimilation of theology as a
science, both in terms of research methodology and conceptual apparatus, as
well as standards of cognitively valuable knowledge (Turek 2001). Turek, unlike
Heller, looks for an opportunity to guarantee the impact of the natural
sciences on theology, at the same time assuming their epistemological and
methodological separateness. According to Turek a confirmation of the
separatist vision can be seen in the success of the natural sciences, that is
to say, in the process of growing autonomy of different knowledge disciplines
at the beginning of modern times. Polak suggests that from the standpoint of
the separation model, we have a number of reasons to not sacrifice a
well-developed methodology. Indeed, there is no already formulated and tested
method that could replace the current one and the choice of an unverified
methodology instead of a well-functioning one does not seem justified.
Moreover, overcoming the barriers would perhaps mean resuming the
physical-theology program and the risk of the argument “God of the gaps” (Oleksowicz
2014).
Polak clarifies
that the theology of science in separationistic spirit would be a specific
philosophical meta-reflection on science and theology. It would therefore be
part of philosophy, but its subject matter would come both from theology and
science and its goal would be to come up with bridging interpolations,
connecting views of the worlds of science and theology. It would be a specific
type of induction metaphysics operating on extrapolations of scientific and
theological knowledge. It would differ from classic metaphysics by its
tentative conclusions and the need of their constant revision; it would be
similar to classic ontology through generally seeking knowledge and having the
objective to deliver a consistent, rational view of the world. Its theological
character would be decided by the fact of using the Revelation (developed as a
theological view of the world) as a source of data (Polak 2015, 51-54).
Therefore, a theology of science, by working through the contact point of views
of the world built around different notional constructs, could critically
investigate the philosophical foundations of science and theology, pointing out
essential differences in assumptions and notional constructs.
2. Objections and questions to
be answered
After providing a
preliminary definition of the theology of science, its principal issues and
some methodological caveats, some objections and questions emerge.
As seen in the case
of an interactionist paradigm, the theology of science becomes an
interdisciplinary/multidisciplinary branch, the status of which is not so
clear. Polak suggests that considerations on theology of science within a
separationistic model should begin with pointing out specific problems that it
is supposed to consider. An essential problem would likely be a confrontation
between the view of the world as presented by nature sciences with theology’s
view of the world. The idea of the world can be understood as a hermeneutical
category, that is, a complete vision of general beliefs about man, the world and
knowledge; a type of specific intellectual background, a specific knowledge of
all types of cognitive behaviour of human beings (Liana 2010, 71). On the other
hand, an important problem is the issue of view of the world itself, i.e. it is
difficult today to show one coherent view of the world provided by the
sciences. The specialization of the sciences and fragmentariness of proposed
views of the world is problematic (Polak 2015, 47-51). What answer could the
theology of science give to the problem of the fragmentariness of science and
partial views of the world? Could different ontologies proposed within
philosophical reflection upon particular sciences form the basis for both
theology and science interpretation? As it was explained, one of the possible strategies
of the development of the theology of sciences suggests that it should be a
type of meta-scientific (and meta-theological) reflection. In this context, the
theology of science would be understood as an activity on a meta-level, whose
subject would be providing notional constructs of science and theology, and its
essential target would be to individuate elements of the scientific view of the
world that could be accepted as potentially serving towards uncontradiction of
views of the world of theology and science (Polak 2015, 44-47; Strumiłowski
2019).
Furthermore, if we
are considering that a program for the theology of science would lead to an
attempt at evaluating contemporary scientific efforts from a theological point
of view, questions arise such as whether theology is open to external content
coming from current view of the world and if so, how such and opening is to be
understood? Can one give a positive answer to postulate of assimilation of
scientific data in theological analysis? (Mścisławski 2015).
In contemporary
science, the question of the dependence of ontological conclusions upon
physical theories, which are subject to relatively quick changes, is widely
discussed. Therefore, an analysis of the temporality of science and the
dynamics of its development seems to be very important (anticumulativism,
cumulativism). One can, however, ask if the variability of scientific theories
and extremes of their philosophical interpretations would essentially make it
impossible to work out coherent views, and moreover block building another
layer of theology of science upon science and its philosophy? (Janusz 2015).
Would it therefore make any sense to build theological conclusions upon such a
volatile foundation of ontological analysis?
It seems that an intermediary layer of dialogue
between sciences and theology should use the achievements of philosophy of
science and philosophy of mathematics, considering the fact that mathematical
tools are today often the only possible means of scientific exploration. In
regard to completion of ontology of science, Dadaczyński suggests that the
development of theology of science could be a completion of ontology of
mathematics (Dadaczyński 2015). In this context, this would essentially mean
discussing the relations between universe of mathematical objects and God.
Mathematics itself does not take on the problem of existence and nature of
mathematical objects (extreme realism, conservative realism, conceptualism) –
they are the subject of philosophy of mathematics. Einstein wrote that
“without belief in internal harmony of
the world there could not be any science. Foundation of any scientific research
is a conviction that the world is an orderly and understandable entity, which
is a religious belief” (Einstein 2001). Therefore, the question arises if the
belief about the uniformity of nature or its mathematicality, which is the
basis for any research, is founded on theological ideas? It seems that only
from a broader philosophical-theological perspective can we give full meaning
to the whole immanent that is science.
IV.
Conclusions
The situation in
which theology and science do not have any points of contact and seem to ignore
each other, is all the more dramatic because of the fact that “nothing is more
dangerous of the ignorance of a problem, if not the ignorance of a solution” (Koyré
2018, 15). The main idea of the theology of science project is to avoid such a
risk and offer a new opportunity for dialogue between theology and contemporary
science.
From analysis of the
basic ideas of the theology of science result four main proposals for the
discipline.
The first one
concerns the problem of the temporal dimension of scientific progress. There
are many thinkers who propose a philosophical analysis of the nature of
empirical theories, of the objects that they describe, but also on the nature
of scientific evolution (Marcacci 2018b, 205-218). From the current
philosophical reflection on science, contrary to the standard view of science
dominating in the first half of the 20th century, it appears that
scientific theories are never absolute and given once and for all. If
scientific theories change, then the world they describe also changes. Unlike
the metaphysical theories of the past, the ontologies proposed within the
philosophical discourse on science rather have a local and non-comprehensive
character, therefore the question remains about the use of different local
(partial) ontologies within the theological reflection that should recognize
the fact that scientific rationality is expressed contextually, historically.
Secondly, it seems
that what remains fundamental for theological reflection is not so much the
specific way in which an empirical data is described, but rather the fact that
nature presents itself as understandable, intelligible. In fact, in Heller’s
thought one can note the importance of the Logos (sense), which
consequently leads to the search for a coherent world view, which is called by
Heller as rationality/mathematicality of the world. This unifying theological
vision would involve different cognitive contributions and would remain open to
constant changes, showing the dynamic character of our world view. In this
context, theology must start from Revelation and speak about science with its
language, indicating the areas that the scientific method does not recognize
(e.g. the problem of creation). Therefore the second proposal concerns the
in-depth study of the theological concepts of the world in their
historical-conceptual development, in order to better distinguish in them the
invariant elements (a revealed datum) from the variant ones (historically
conditioned). This proposal assumes the hierarchization of theological
statements. In other words, not all theological truths are as important and
unchangeable as dogmas.
Thirdly, it should
be noted that the discussion on the nature and purpose of the theology of
science, provided by Bugajak and Szczurek, went in a very promising and
profitable direction, in the sense that it reveals the attempt to provide some
suggestions of an epistemological nature to establish the theology of science.
Going in this direction, it seems that the main question to be answered is:
“how to build the theology of science?”. It would be too naive to find the
answer by proposing only case studies, or by trying to provide the theological
interpretation of some scientific data. In fact these are not lacking in the
field of Science and Religion. But
case studies are often limited to some kind of “fragmentary” work and could
lead once again to problems related to the “God of the gaps” argument.
Therefore, the third proposal suggests a specification of how the methodology
of the theology of science should work in order to be able to dialogue with the
problems of today’s science (e.g. the problem of intelligibility, causality and
scientific explanation). One may intuit that in this context that the theology
of science could be interpreted as the critical analysis of the conditions of
possibility of philosophical and scientific thought. In other words, it seems
that the theology of science could be interpreted first of all as the critical
analysis of the foundational paradigm present in science and philosophy (Grenz
and Franke 2001) and as the consequence can cause widening the perspective of
human rationality (Giostra 2019). This critical approach would not necessarily
mean philosophical/theological relativism or scepticism, but would bring the
opportunity for a fruitful, dynamic dialogue based on the fact that for
theologian the Universe is vestigium. The problem of the intelligibility
(comprehensibility) of the world is certainly to be further investigated (de
Regt 2017).
Fourthly, theology
of science can bring about a return in philosophy to a sort of optimistic and
realistic idea of human existence in the world (Woźniak 2007, 67-70). It is
because theology of science offers the type of rationality that is the result
of act of accepting in trust God’s Revelation. On the contrary, modern
philosophy was born as the consequence of systematic doubt. Therefore theology
can help philosophy and science discover contemplating and receptive nature of
human reason. Theology as the science of sense can save human reason from the
slavery of its own categories, concepts, laws and teach us how ask new
questions and patiently look for answers.
References
Alai, M. 2017. “The Debates on
Scientific Realism Today: Knowledge and Objectivity in Science”. In Varieties of Scientific Realism. Objectivity
and Truth in Science, ed. E. Agazzi, 30-38. Dordrecht-Heidelberg-London-New
York: Springer.
Barbour, I.G. 1997. Religion and science. Historical and
contemporary issues. San Francisco: Harper.
Bugajak, G. 2015. “Naturalizm nauki a działanie Boga w świecie”.
In Teologia nauki, eds. J. Mączka, P.
Urbańczyk, 145-172. Kraków: Copernicus Center Press.
Dadaczyński, J. 2015. “O niektórych (możliwych) obszarach badań
teologii nauki”. In Teologia
nauki, eds. J. Mączka, P. Urbańczyk, 75-94. Kraków: Copernicus Center
Press.
de Regt, H.W. 2017.
“Understanding Scientific Understanding”. New York: Oxford University Press.
Einstein, A. 2001. Pisma filozoficzne, transl. K.
Napiórkowski. Warszawa: De Agostini. Quotation from: A. Świeżyński, 2012. Filozofia cudu. Warszawa: Wydawnictwo
UKSW.
Giostra, A. 2019. “Benedict XVI and
the Limits of Scientific Learning”. Scientia et Fides 7(1)/2019:
97-110.
Grenz, S.J. and J.R. Franke.
2001. Beyond Foundationalism. Shaping
Theology in a Postmodern Context. Lousville-Kentucky: Westminster John Knox
Press.
Heller, M. 1987a. “Ewolucja pojęcia masy”. In Filozofować w kontekście nauki, eds. M.
Heller, A. Michalik, J. Życiński, 152-163. Kraków: Polskie Towarzystwo
Teologiczne.
Heller, M. 1987b. “Doświadczenie granic”. In Filozofować w kontekście Nauki, eds. M.
Heller, A. Michalik, J. Życiński, 53-59. Kraków: Polskie Towarzystwo
Teologiczne.
Heller, M. 1997. “Scientific Rationality and Christian Logos”.
In Physics, philosophy and theology: A
Common Quest for Understanding, eds.
R.J. Russell, G.V. Coyne, W.R. Stoeger, 141-150. Vatican State: Vatican
Observatory.
Heller, M. 2006. Filozofia i wszechświat. Kraków:
Universitas.
Heller, M. 2007. Science and Theology, in The Blackwell Companion to Catholicism, eds.
J. Buckley, F. Bauershmidt, T. Pomplum, 477-489. Malden-Oxford-Carlton: Blackwell
Publishing.
Heller, M. 2008a. “Statement
by Professor Michał Heller at the Templeton Prize News Conference, March, 12th,
2008”. Philosophical Problems in Science
XLIII (2008): 13-17.
Heller, M. 2008b. Sens
życia i sens wszechświata. Studia z teologii współczesnej. Tarnów: Biblos.
Heller, M. 2014. Nowa fizyka i nowa teologia. Kraków: Copernicus
Center Press.
Heller, M. 2015a. Moralność myślenia. Kraków: Copernicus Center
Press.
Heller, M. 2015b. “Wstęp do teologii nauki”. In Teologia
nauki, eds. J. Mączka, P. Urbańczyk, 13-22. Kraków: Copernicus Center Press.
Heller, M. 2016. Wierzę,
żeby zrozumieć. Rozmawiają Wojciech Bonowicz, Bartosz Brożek, Zbigniew Liana. Kraków: Copernicus Center Press-Znak.
Janusz, R. 2015. “Nauka i wiara – naturalne i nadprzyrodzone”.
In Teologia Nauki, eds. J. Mączka, P.
Urbańczyk, 109-126. Kraków: Copernicus Center Press.
Koyré, A. 2018. Miracoli e verifiche. Due testi inediti su
teologia e scienza, ed. P. Redondi, transl. G. Ibba. Bologna: Marietti
1820.
Ladyman, J. 2014. “Structural
Realism”. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/structural-realism/.
Lambert, D. 2002. “Le figure del dialogo scienza-teologia:
ostacoli e prospettive”. In Dio e
la natura, eds. R. Martìnez, and J.J. Sanguineti. Roma: Armando.
Lambert, D. 1999. Sciences et théologie. Les figures d’un
dialogue. Presses Universitaires de Namur: Éditions Lessius.
Liana, Z. 2010. “Teologia a naukowe obrazy świata”. In
Wiara i nauka: materiały z sesji naukowej
i dyskusji panelowej: IV Dni Jana Pawła II, ed. J. Mączka. Kraków:
Wydawnictwo Uniwersytetu Jagiellońskiego.
Macek, W.M. 2010. Teologia nauki według księdza Michała
Hellera. Warszawa: Wydawnictwo UKSW.
Macek, W.M. 2011. “Teologia nauki”. In Oblicza racjonalności. Wokół myśli Michała Hellera, eds. B. Brożek, J. Mączka, W.P. Grygiel, M.L. Hohol, 203-238. Kraków: Copernicus Center
Press.
Marcacci, F. 2018a. “Creazione e cosmologia scientifica. Problemi epistemologici e
opportunità speculative”. Aquinas
LXI (1-2)/2018: 147-164.
Marcacci, F. 2018b. Cieli in contraddizione. Giovanni Battista
Riccioli e il terzo sistema del Mondo. Perugia: Accademia Nazionale di
Scienze Lettere e Arti Modena.
Mścisławski, Ł. 2015. “Wartość kontyngencji”. In Teologia Nauki, eds. J. Mączka, P.
Urbańczyk, 57-73. Kraków: Copernicus Center Press.
Oleksowicz, M. 2014. “Dyskusja nad
argumentem «God of the gaps»”. Scientia
et Fides 2(1)/ 2014: 99-123.
Olszewski, A. 2015. “Punkty styczności pomiędzy teologią a nauką”.
In Teologia Nauki, eds. J. Mączka, P.
Urbańczyk, 95-108. Kraków: CC Press.
Pedersen, O. 1990. “Historical interaction between science and
religion”. In Science and Religion,
eds. J. Fennema, I. Paul. Springer: Dordrecht.
Pedersen, O. 1997. Konflikt czy symbioza. Z dziejów relacji
między nauką a teologią, transl. W. Skoczny. Tarnów: Biblos.
Pietsch, W. 2011. “The
Underdetermination Debate: How Lack of History Leads to Bad Philosophy”. In Integrating History and Philosophy of
Science. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, eds. S. Mauskopf, T.
Schmaltz, vol 263, 83-106. Dordrecht: Springer.
Polak, P. 2015. “Teologia nauki w perspektywie metodologicznej”.
In Teologia nauki, eds. J. Mączka, P.
Urbańczyk, 25-56. Kraków: Copernicus Center Press.
Roszak, P. 2014. Credibilidad e identidad. En torno a la Teología de la Fe en santo Tomás de Aquino. Pamplona: Eunsa.
Russell, R.J. 2002. “Dialogue, Science
and Theology”. In Interdisciplinary
Encyclopedia of Religion and Science, eds. G. Tanzella-Nitti, I. Colagé, A.
Strumia. doi: 10.17421/2037-2329-2002-RR-1.
Strumiłowski, J.
“Complementarity and cohesion of the sophiologic and scientific vision of creation”.
Scientia et Fides 7(1)/2019: 207-225.
Szczurek, J.D. 2015. “Teologia nauki. Poszukiwanie struktury”. In Teologia
nauki, eds. J. Mączka, P. Urbańczyk, 127-142. Kraków: Copernicus Center
Press.
Turek, J. 2001.
“Metodologiczne ograniczenia prób unaukowienia teologii”. Roczniki Filozoficzne LIX (2001), n. 2.
Woźniak, R. 2007. Przyszłość, teologia, społeczeństwo.
Kraków: WAM.
Życiński, J. 1984. “W poszukiwaniu teologii nauki”. In Nauka-religia-dzieje: II Seminarium
Interdyscyplinarne w Castel Gandolfo, 6-9 września 1982 roku, eds. J.A.
Janik, P Lenartowicz. Kraków: Wydział Filozoficzny Towarzystwa Jezusowego.
Michał Oleksowicz
Department of Philosophy
Faculty of Theology
Nicolas Copernicus University
ul. Gagarina 37
87-100 Torun (Poland)
https://orcid.org/0000-0001-5591-0579